Science <-> Theosophy >?< Intelligent Design <-> Evolution-- where's it all going?
Feb 18, 2006 05:35 PM
by leonmaurer
Friends,
Here's a new take on "Intelligent Design" from a scientific/technological
point of view.
Is science getting closer and closer to theosophy, or is this just another
stretch of their speculations to reinforce materialism in the face of Darwin
bashing creationism? Or is it simply a means to get on Kurzweil's "Singularity"
bandwagon and confirm his prophesy that future bionic beings, half man half
machine with super intelligence and eternal life is the goal of evolution? It
even implies that such supermen will be wise enough to build this entire
Cosmos. I wonder how far they can take such circular reasoning before it spirals
down so tight it compresses into the zero point and explodes in their faces? <
/:-)>
Amazing how far materialists can go to massage their presumption that matter
is everything.:-) But, they are, in a way, getting closer and closer to a
more or less atheistic theosophical philosophy. All they have to do is answer
the question of how this coming super intelligence jump starts this particular
universe, and where its total mass energy comes from -- besides, telling us
where and from what their consciousness (awareness, will, etc.) originates in
the first place? :-)
How many other questions can we ask that might get them to turn around and
see it all from the inside out rather than from the outside in?
Much food for thought, eh?
Leon
http://www.kurzweilai.net/index.html?flash=1
Biocosm, The New Scientific Theory of Evolution
Intelligent Life Is the Architect of the Universe
by James N. Gardner
Why is the universe life-friendly? Columbia physicist Brian Greene says it's
the deepest question in all of science. Cosmologist Paul Davies agrees,
calling it the biggest of the Big Questions.
This is a transcript of a lecture originally delivered at Hayden Planetarium,
as part of the "Distinguished Authors in Astronomy" lecture series. Reprinted
on KurzweilAI.net February 10, 2006.
It is, in the view of Columbia physicist Brian Greene, the deepest question
in all of science. Renowned cosmologist Paul Davies agrees, calling it the
biggest of the Big Questions.
And just what is this momentous question?
Not the mystery of life's origin, though the profundity of that particular
puzzle prompted Charles Darwin to remark that it was probably forever beyond the
pale of human comprehension. A dog, Darwin commented famously, might as
easily contemplate the mind of Newton.
Not the inscrutable manner in which consciousness emerges from the
interaction and interconnection of neurons in the human skull, though a cascade of Nobel
prizes will undoubtedly reward the teams of neuroscientists who achieve
progress in understanding this phenomenon.
And not even the future course of biological and cultural evolution on planet
Earth, though the great Darwinian river is surely carving a course that
today's most visionary evolutionary theorist will have difficulty even imagining.
No, the question is more profound, more fundamental, less tractable than any
of these. It is this-why is the universe life-friendly?
Life-friendly, you might ask incredulously? The universe is life-friendly?
The heck it is!
We have been taught since childhood that the universe is a horrifyingly
hostile place. Violent black holes, planets and moons searing with unbearable heat
or deep-frozen at temperatures that make Antarctica look tropical, and the
vastness of interstellar space dooming us to perpetual physical isolation from
our nearest starry neighbors-this is the depressing picture of the cosmos beyond
Earth that dominates the popular imagination.
This vision is profoundly wrong at a fundamental level. As scientists are now
beginning to realize to their astonishment, the truly amazing thing about our
universe is how strangely and improbably life-friendly or anthropic it is. As
Cambridge evolutionary biologist Simon Conway Morris puts it in his new book
Life's Solution, “On a cosmic scale, it is now widely appreciated that even
trivial differences in the starting conditions [of the cosmos] would lead to an
unrecognizable and uninhabitable universe.”
Simply put, if the Big Bang had detonated with slightly greater force, the
cosmos would be essentially empty by now. If the primordial explosion had
propelled the initial payload of cosmic raw materials outward with slightly lesser
force, the universe would long ago have recollapsed in a Big Crunch. In neither
case would human beings or other life forms have had time to evolve.
As Stephen Hawking asks, “Why is the universe so close to the dividing line
between collapsing again and expanding indefinitely? In order to be as close as
we are now, the rate of expansion early on had to be chosen fantastically
accurately.”
It is not only the rate of cosmic expansion that appears to have been
selected, with phenomenal precision, in order to render our universe fit for
carbon-based life and the emergence of intelligence. A multitude of other factors are
fine-tuned with fantastic exactitude to a degree that renders the cosmos
almost spookily bio-friendly. Some of the universe's life-friendly attributes
include the odd proclivity of stellar nucleosynthesis-the process by which simple
elements like hydrogen and helium are transmuted into heavier elements in the
hearts of giant supernovae-to yield copious quantities of carbon, the chemical
epicenter of life as we know it.
As British astronomer Fred Hoyle pointed out, in order for carbon to exist in
the abundant quantities that we observe throughout the cosmos, the mechanism
of stellar nucleosynthesis must be exquisitely fine-tuned in a very special
way.
Yet another bio-friendly feature of the cosmos is the physical dimensionality
of our universe: why are there just three extended dimensions of space rather
one or two or even the ten spatial dimensions contemplated by M-theory? As
has been known for more than a century, in any other dimensional setup, stable
planetary orbits would be impossible and life would not have time to get
started before planets skittered off into deep space or plunged into their suns.
For centuries, it seemed that the dimensionality of the universe-three
dimensions of space plus one dimension of time-was a matter of axiomatic truth.
Rather like the propositions of geometry. In fact, precisely like the propositions
of geometry. That was before the birth of superstring theory, and its
successor, M-theory. I am going to get into M-theory more deeply in a moment but for
now I want to highlight its insistence on the fact that there are, in fact,
ten dimensions of space and one dimension of time. The mystery is why only three
of the spatial dimensions got inflated into cosmic proportions by the Big
Bang while the remaining seven stayed inconceivably minuscule. If anything else
had happened-if only two spatial dimensions had been inflated or if four had
been inflated-then the universe would not have been set up to allow the
emergence of life and mind as we know them.
Collectively, this stunning set of coincidences render the universe eerily
fit for life and intelligence. And the coincidences are built into the
fundamental fabric of our reality. As British Astronomer Royal Sir Martin Rees says, “
There are deep connections between stars and atoms, between the cosmos and the
microworld . . . . Our emergence and survival depend on very special 'tuning'
of the cosmos.” Or, as the eminent Princeton physicist John Wheeler put it, “
It is not only that man is adapted to the universe. The universe is adapted to
man. Imagine a universe in which one or another of the fundamental
dimensionless constants of physics is altered by a few percent one way or the other? Man
could never come into being in such a universe.”
Scientists have been aware of this set of puzzles for decades and have given
it name-the anthropic cosmological principle-but there is a new urgency to the
quest for a plausible explanation because of two very recent discoveries-the
first at nature's largest scale and the second at its tiniest.
The first was the discovery of dark energy, which resulted from the
observations of supernovae at extreme distances. Contrary to all expectations, the
evidence showed that the expansion of the universe was speeding up, not slowing
down. No one knows what is causing this phenomenon, although speculative
explanations like leakage of gravity into extra unseen dimensions are beginning to
show up in the scientific literature.
But for our purposes, what is particularly puzzling is why the strength of
dark energy-which the new Wilkinson microwave probe has revealed to be the
predominant constituent of our cosmos-is so vanishingly small, yet not quite zero.
If it were even a tad stronger, you see, the universe would have been emptied
long ago, scrubbed clean of stars and galaxies well before life and
intelligence could evolve.
The second discovery occurred in the realm of M-theory, whose previous
incarnation was known as superstring theory. Those of you who have read Brian
Greene's terrific book The Elegant Universe or watched the Nova series based on it
will know that M-theory posits that subatomic particles like quarks, electrons
and neutrinos are really just different modes of vibration of tiny
one-dimensional strings of energy. But what is truly strange about M-theory is that it
allows a vast landscape of possible vibration modes of superstrings, only a tiny
fraction of which correspond to anything like the sub-atomic particle world
we observe and that is described by what is known as the Standard Model of
particle physics.
Just how big is this landscape of possible alternative models of particle
physics allowed by M-theory? According to Stanford physicist and superstring
pioneer Leonard Susskind, the mathematical landscape is horrifyingly gigantic,
permitting 10500 power different and distinct environments, none of which appears
to be mathematically favored, let alone foreordained by the theory. And in
virtually none of those other mathematically permissible environments would
matter and energy have possessed the qualities that are necessary for stars,
galaxies and carbon-based living creatures to have emerged from the primordial
chaos.
This is, as Susskind says, an intellectual cataclysm of the first magnitude
because it seems to deprive our most promising new theory of fundamental
physics-M-theory-of the power to uniquely predict the emergence of anything remotely
resembling our universe. As Susskind puts it, the picture of the universe
that is emerging from the deep mathematical recesses of M-theory is not an “
elegant universe” at all! It's a Rube Goldberg device, cobbled together by some
unknown process in a supremely improbable manner that just happens to render the
whole ensemble miraculously fit for life. In the words of University of
California theoretical physicist Steve Giddings, “No longer can we follow the dream
of discovering the unique equations that predict everything we see, and
writing them on a single page.” Or a tee-shirt! “Predicting the constants of nature
becomes a messy environmental problem. It has the complications of biology.”
Note the key word Giddings uses-“biology”-because we will be coming back to
it shortly.
This really is, as Brian Greene says, the deepest problem in all of science.
It really is, as Paul Davies says, the biggest of the Big Questions: why is
the universe life-friendly?
If we put to one side theological approaches to this ultimate issue, what
rational pathways forward are on offer from the scientific community? I suggest
that three basic approaches are available. Two are familiar while the third is
radically novel.
The first approach is to continue searching patiently for a unique final
theory-something that you really could write on your tee-shirt like E = mc2-which
might yet, against the odds, emerge from M-theory or one of its competitors
(like loop quantum gravity) aspiring to the status of a so-called “theory of
everything.” This is the fond hope of virtually every professional theoretical
physicist, including those who have been driven to desperation by the
horrendously messy and complex landscape of theoretically possible M-theory-allowed
universes that distresses Susskind and other superstring theorists. Perhaps the
laws and constants of nature-an ensemble the late New York Academy of Sciences
president and physicist Heinz Pagels dubbed the cosmic code-will, in the end,
turn out to be uniquely specified by mathematics and thus subject to no
conceivable variation. Perhaps the ultimate equations will someday slide out of the
mind of a new colossus of physics as slickly and beautifully as E = mc2 emerged
from Einstein's brain. Perhaps, but that appears to be an increasingly
unlikely prospect.
A second approach, born of desperation on the part of Susskind and others, is
to overlay a refinement of Big Bang inflation theory called eternal chaotic
inflation with an explanatory approach that has been traditionally reviled by
most scientists which is known as the weak anthropic principle. The weak
anthropic principle merely states in tautological fashion that since human observers
inhabit this particular universe, it must perforce be life-friendly or it
would not contain any observers resembling ourselves. Eternal chaotic inflation,
invented by Russian-born physicist Andrei Linde, asserts that instead of just
one Big Bang there are, always have been, and always will be, zillions of Big
Bangs going off in inaccessible regions all the time. These Big Bangs create
zillions of new universes constantly and the whole ensemble constitutes a
multiverse.
Now here's what happens when these two ideas-eternal chaotic inflation and
the weak anthropic principle-are joined together. In each Big Bang, the laws,
constants and the physical dimensionality of nature come out differently. In
some, dark energy is stronger. In some, dark energy is weaker. In some, gravity
is stronger. In some, gravity is weaker. This happens, according to
M-theory-based cosmology, because the 10-dimensional physical shapes in which
superstrings vibrate-known as Calabi-Yau shapes-evolve randomly and chaotically at the
moment of each new Big Bang. The laws and constants of nature are constantly
reshuffled by this process, like a cosmic deck of cards.
And here's the crucial part. Once in a blue moon, this random process of
eternal chaotic inflation will yield a winning hand, as judged from the
perspective of whether a particular new universe is life-friendly. That outcome will be
pure chance-one lucky roll of the dice in an unimaginably vast cosmic crap
shoot with 10500 unfavorable outcomes for every winning turn.
Our universe was a big winner, of course, in the cosmic lottery. Our cosmos
was dealt a royal flush. Here is how the eminent Nobel laureate Steve Weinberg
explained this scenario in a New York Review of Books essay a couple of years
ago: “The expanding cloud of billions of galaxies that we call the big bang
may be just one fragment of a much larger universe in which big bangs go off all
the time, each one with different values for the fundamental constants.” It
is no more a mystery that our particular branch of the multiverse exhibits
life-friendly characteristics, according to Weinberg, than that life evolved on
the hospitable Earth “rather than some horrid place, like Mercury or Pluto.”
If you find this scenario unsatisfactory-the weak anthropic principle
superimposed on Andrei Linde's theory of eternal chaotic inflation-I can assure you
that you are not alone. To most scientists, offering the tautological
explanation that since human observers inhabit this particular universe, it must
necessarily be life-friendly or else it would not contain any observers resembling
ourselves is anathema. It just sounds like giving up.
In my view, there are two primary problems with the Weinberg/Susskind
approach. First, universes spawned by Big Bangs other than our own are inaccessible
from our own universe, at least with the experimental techniques currently
available to scientists. So the approach appears to be untestable, perhaps
untestable in principle. And testability is the hallmark of genuine science,
distinguishing it from fields of inquiry like metaphysics and theology.
Second, the Weinberg/Susskind approach extravagantly violates the mediocrity
principle. The mediocrity principle, a mainstay of scientific theorizing since
Copernicus, is a statistically based rule of thumb that, absent contrary
evidence, a particular sample (Earth, for instance, or our particular universe)
should be assumed to be a typical example of the ensemble of which it is a part.
The Weinberg/Susskind approach flagrantly flouts the mediocrity principle.
Instead, their approach simply takes refuge in a brute, unfathomable mystery-the
conjectured lucky roll of the dice in a crap game of eternal chaotic
inflation-and declines to probe seriously into the possibility of a naturalistic
cosmic evolutionary process that has the capacity to yield a life-friendly set of
physical laws and constants on a nonrandom basis. It is as if Charles Darwin,
contemplating the famous tangled bank (the arresting visual image with which he
concludes The Origin of Species), had confessed not a magnificent obsession
with gaining an understanding of the mysterious natural processes that had
yielded “endless forms most beautiful and most wonderful,” but rather a smug
satisfaction that of course the earthly biosphere must have somehow evolved in a
just-so manner mysteriously friendly to humans and other currently living
species, or else Darwin and other humans would not be around to contemplate it!
Indeed, the situation that confronts cosmologists today is eerily reminiscent
of that which faced biologists before Charles Darwin propounded his
revolutionary theory of evolution. Darwin confronted the seemingly miraculous
phenomenon of a fine-tuned natural order in which every creature and plant appeared to
occupy a unique and well-designed niche. Refusing to surrender to the brute
mystery posed by the appearance of nature's design, Darwin masterfully deployed
the art of metaphor to elucidate a radical hypothesis-the origin of species
through natural selection-that explained the apparent miracle as a natural
phenomenon.
The metaphor furnished by the familiar process of artificial selection was
Darwin's crucial stepping stone. Indeed, the practice of artificial selection
through plant and animal breeding was the primary intellectual model that guided
Darwin in his quest to solve the mystery of the origin of species and to
demonstrate in principle the plausibility of his theory that variation and natural
selection were the prime movers responsible for the phenomenon of speciation.
So, too, today a few venturesome cosmologists have begun to use the same
poetic tool utilized by Darwin-the art of metaphorical thinking-to develop novel
intellectual models that might offer a logical explanation for what appears to
be an unfathomable mystery: the apparent fine-tuning of the cosmos.
The cosmological metaphor chosen by these iconoclastic theorists is life
itself. What if life, they ask in the spirit the great Belgian biologist and Nobel
laureate Christian de Duve, were not a cosmic accident but the essential
reality at the very heart of the elegant machinery of the universe? What if
Darwin's principle of natural selection were merely a tiny fractal embodiment of a
universal life-giving principle that drives the evolution of stars, galaxies,
and the cosmos itself?
This, as you may have guessed, is the headline summarizing the third (and
radically novel) approach to answering the biggest of the Big Questions: why is
the universe life-friendly? It is the approach outlined at length in my new
book BIOCOSM.
Before I get into this third approach in more detail, I want to say something
upfront about scientific speculation. The approach I am about to outline for
you is intentionally and forthrightly speculative. Following the example of
Darwin, I have attempted to crudely frame a radically new explanatory paradigm
well before all of the required building materials and construction tools are
at hand. Darwin had not the slightest clue, for instance, that DNA is the
molecular device used by all life-forms on Earth to accomplish the feat of what he
called “inheritance.” Indeed, as cell biologist Kenneth R. Miller noted in
Finding Darwin's God, “Charles Darwin worked in almost total ignorance of the
fields we now call genetics, cell biology, molecular biology, and biochemistry.”
Nonetheless, Darwin managed to put forward a plausible theoretical framework
that succeeded magnificently despite the fact that it was utterly dependent on
hypothesized but completely unknown mechanisms of genetic transmission.
As Darwin's example shows, plausible and deliberate speculation plays an
essential role in the advancement of science. Speculation is the means by which
new scientific paradigms are initially constructed, to be either abandoned later
as wrong-headed detours or vindicated as the seeds of scientific revolutions.
Another important lesson drawn from Darwin's experience is important to note
at the outset. Answering the question of why the most eminent geologists and
naturalists had, until shortly before publication of The Origin of Species,
disbelieved in the mutability of species, Darwin responded that this false
conclusion was “almost inevitable as long as the history of the world was thought to
be of short duration.” It was geologist Charles Lyell's speculations on the
immense age of Earth that provided the essential conceptual framework for
Darwin's new theory. Lyell's vastly expanded stretch of geological time provided an
ample temporal arena in which the forces of natural selection could sculpt
and reshape the species of Earth and achieve nearly limitless variation.
The central point is that collateral advances in sciences seemingly far
removed from cosmology can help dissipate the intellectual limitations imposed by
common sense and naïve human intuition. And, in an uncanny reprise of the
Lyell/Darwin intellectual synergy, it is a realization of the vastness of time and
history that gives rise to the crucial insight. Only in this instance, the
vastness of which I speak is the vastness of future time and future history. In
particular, sharp attention must be paid to the key conclusion of Princeton
physicist John Wheeler: most of the time available for life and intelligence to
achieve their ultimate capabilities lie in the distant cosmic future, not in
the cosmic past. As cosmologist Frank Tipler bluntly stated, “Almost all of
space and time lies in the future. By focusing attention only on the past and
present, science has ignored almost all of reality. Since the domain of scientific
study is the whole of reality, it is about time science decided to study the
future evolution of the universe.”
That is exactly what I have attempted to do in BIOCOSM in order to explore,
in a tentative way, a possible third pathway to an answer to the biggest of the
Big Questions. I call that third pathway the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis.
Originally presented in peer-reviewed scientific papers published in
Complexity, Acta Astronautica, and the Journal of the British Interplanetary Society,
my Selfish Biocosm hypothesis suggests that in attempting to explain the
linkage between life, intelligence and the anthropic qualities of the cosmos, most
mainstream scientists have, in essence, been peering through the wrong end of
the telescope. The hypothesis asserts that life and intelligence are, in fact,
the primary cosmological phenomena and that everything else-the constants of
nature, the dimensionality of the universe, the origin of carbon and other
elements in the hearts of giant supernovas, the pathway traced by biological
evolution-is secondary and derivative. In the words of Martin Rees, my approach is
based on the proposition that “what we call the fundamental constants-the
numbers that matter to physicists-may be secondary consequences of the final
theory, rather than direct manifestations of its deepest and most fundamental
level.”
I began developing the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis as an attempt to supply two
essential elements missing from a novel model of cosmological evolution put
forward by astrophysicist Lee Smolin. Smolin had come up with the intriguing
suggestion that black holes are gateways to new “baby universes” and that a
kind of Darwinian population dynamic rewards those universes most adept at
producing black holes with the greatest number of progeny. Proliferating populations
of baby universes emerging from the loins (metaphorically speaking) of black
hole-rich “mother universes” thus come to dominate the total population of
the “multiverse”-a theoretical ensemble of all mother and baby universes. Black
hole-prone universes also happen to coincidentally exhibit anthropic
qualities, according to Smolin, thus accounting for the bio-friendly nature of the “
average” cosmos in the ensemble, more or less as an incidental side-effect.
This was a thrilling conjecture because for the first time it posited a
cosmic evolutionary process endowed with what economists call a utility function
(i.e., a value that was maximized by the hypothesized evolutionary process,
which in the case of Smolin's conjecture was black hole maximization).
However, Smolin's approach was seriously flawed. As the computer genius John
von Neumann demonstrated in a famous 1948 Caltech lecture entitled “On the
General and Logical Theory of Automata,” any self-reproducing object (mouse,
bacterium, human or baby universe) must, as a matter of inexorable logic, possess
four essential elements:
1. A blueprint, providing the plan for construction of offspring;
2. A factory, to carry out the construction;
3. A controller, to ensure that the factory follows the plan; and
4. A duplicating machine, to transmit a copy of the blueprint to the
offspring.
In the case of Smolin's hypothesis, one could logically equate the collection
of physical laws and constants that prevail in our universe with a von
Neumann blueprint and the universe at large with a kind of enormous von Neumann
factory. But what could possibly serve as a von Neumann controller or a von
Neumann duplicating machine? My goal was to rescue Smolin's basic innovation-a
cosmic evolutionary model that incorporated a discernible utility function-by
proposing scientifically plausible candidates for the two missing von Neumann
elements.
The hypothesis I developed was based on a set of conjectures put forward by
Martin Rees, John Wheeler, Freeman Dyson, John Barrow, Frank Tipler, and Ray
Kurzweil. Their futuristic visions suggested collectively that the ongoing
process of biological and technological evolution was sufficiently robust,
powerful, and open-ended that, in the very distant future, a cosmologically extended
biosphere could conceivably exert a global influence on the physical state of
the entire cosmos. Think of this idea as the Gaia principle extended
universe-wide.
A synthesis of these insights lead me directly to the central claim of the
Selfish Biocosm hypothesis: that the ongoing process of biological and
technological emergence, governed by still largely unknown laws of complexity, could
function as a von Neumann controller and that a cosmologically extended
biosphere could serve as a von Neumann duplicating machine in a conjectured process of
cosmological replication.
I went on to speculate that the means by which the hypothesized cosmological
replication process could occur was through the fabrication of baby universes
by highly evolved intelligent life forms. These hypothesized baby universes
would themselves be endowed with a cosmic code-an ensemble of physical laws and
constants-that would be life-friendly so as to enable life and ever more
competent intelligence to emerge and eventually to repeat the cosmic reproduction
cycle. Under this scenario, the physical laws and constants serve a cosmic
function precisely analogous to that of DNA in earthly creatures: they furnish a
recipe for the birth and evolution of intelligent life and a blueprint, which
provides the plan for construction of offspring.
I should add that if the fabrication of baby universes, which is the key step
in the hypothesized cosmic reproductive cycle that I just outlined, sounds to
you like outrageous science fiction-an “X-file too far,” in the words of one
of my critics-you should be aware that the topic has begun to be rigorously
explored by such eminent physicists as Andrei Linde of Stanford, Alan Guth of
MIT (who is the father of inflation theory), Martin Rees of Cambridge, eminent
astronomer Edward Harrison, and physicists Lawrence Krauss and Glenn Starkman.
This central claim of the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis offered a radically new
and quite parsimonious explanation for the apparent mystery of an anthropic or
bio-friendly universe. If highly evolved intelligent life is the von Neumann
duplicating machine that the cosmos employs to reproduce itself-if intelligent
life is, in effect, the reproductive organ of the universe-then it is
entirely logical and predictable that the laws and constants of nature should be
rigged in favor of the emergence of life and the evolution of ever more capable
intelligence. Indeed, the existence of such propensity is a falsifiable
prediction of the hypothesis.
Now, at this point you are probably saying to yourself, “Wow, with a theory
that crazy and radical, this Gardner fellow must have been shunned by the
scientific establishment.” And indeed some mainstream scientists have commented
that the ideas advanced in my book BIOCOSM are impermissibly speculative or
impossible to verify. A few have hurled what scientists view as the ultimate
epithet-that my theory constitutes metaphysics instead of genuine science.
On the other hand, some of the brightest and most far-sighted scientists have
been extremely encouraging. John Barrow and Freeman Dyson have offered
favorable comments and reviews. In particular, BIOCOSM has received outspoken
endorsements from Sir Martin Rees (the UK Astronomer Royal and winner of the top
scientific prize in the world for cosmology) and Paul Davies (the prominent
astrophysicist and author and winner of the Templeton Prize).
As I continue to explore this hypothesis in the future, what will be of
utmost interest to me and my sympathizers is whether it can generate what
scientists call falsifiable implications. Falsifiabiliy or testability of claims,
remember, is the hallmark of genuine science, distinguishing it from metaphysics
and faith-based belief systems.
I believe that the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis does qualify as a genuine
scientific conjecture on this ground. A key implication of the hypothesis is that
the process of progression of the cosmos through critical thresholds in its
life cycle, while perhaps not strictly inevitable, is relatively robust. One such
critical threshold is the emergence of human-level and higher intelligence,
which is essential to the scaling up of biological and technological processes
to the stage at which those processes could conceivably exert an influence on
the global state of the cosmos.
The conventional wisdom among evolutionary theorists, typified by the
thinking of the late Stephen Jay Gould, is that the abstract probability of the
emergence of anything like human intelligence through the natural process of
biological evolution was vanishingly small. According to this viewpoint, the
emergence of human-level intelligence was a staggeringly improbable contingent event.
A few distinguished contrarians like Simon Conway Morris, Robert Wright, E.
O. Wilson, and Christian de Duve take an opposing position, arguing on the
basis of the pervasive phenomenon of convergent evolution and other evidence that
the appearance of human-level intelligence was highly probable, if not
virtually inevitable. The latter position is consistent with the Selfish Biocosm
hypothesis while the Gould position is not.
In my book BIOCOSM and in a preceding scientific paper delivered at the
International Astronautical Congress, I suggest that the issue of the robustness of
the emergence of human-level and higher intelligence is potentially subject
to experimental resolution by means of at least three realistic tests: SETI
research, artificial life evolution, and the emergence of transhuman computer
intelligence predicted by computer science theorist Ray Kurzweil and others. The
discovery of extraterrestrial intelligence, the discovery of an ability on the
part of artificial life forms that exist and evolve in software environments
to acquire autonomy and intelligence, and the emergence of a capacity on the
part of advanced self-programming computers to attain and then exceed human
levels of intelligence are all falsifiable implications of the Selfish Biocosm
hypothesis because they are consistent with the notion that the emergence of
ever more competent intelligence is a robust natural phenomenon. These tests
don't, of course, conclusively answer the question of whether the hypothesis
correctly describes ultimate reality. But such a level of certainty is not demanded
of any scientific hypothesis in order to qualify it as genuine science.
Let me conclude by asking whether the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis promotes or
demotes the cosmic role of humanity. Have I introduced a new anthropocentrism
into the science of cosmology? If so, then you should be suspect on this basis
alone of my new approach because, as Sigmund Freud pointed out long ago, new
scientific paradigms must meet two distinct criteria to be taken seriously:
they must reformulate our vision of physical reality in a novel and plausible
way and, equally important, they must advance the Copernican project of demoting
human beings from the centerpiece of the universe to the results of natural
processes.
At first blush, the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis may appear to be hopelessly
anthropocentric. Freeman Dyson once famously proclaimed that the seemingly
miraculous coincidences exhibited by the physical laws and constants of inanimate
nature-factors that render the universe so strangely life-friendly-indicated to
him that “the more I examine the universe and study the details of its
architecture, the more evidence I find that the universe in some sense knew we were
coming.” This strong anthropic perspective may seem uplifting and inspiring at
first blush but a careful assessment of the new vision of a bio-friendly
universe revealed by the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis yields a far more sobering
conclusion.
To regard the pageant of life's origin and evolution on Earth as a minor
subroutine in an inconceivably vast ontogenetic process through which the universe
prepares itself for replication is scarcely to place humankind at the
epicenter of creation. Far from offering an anthropocentric view of the cosmos, the
new perspective relegates humanity and its probable progeny species (biological
or mechanical) to the functional equivalents of mitochondria-formerly
free-living bacteria whose special talents were harnessed in the distant past when
they were ingested and then pressed into service as organelles inside eukaryotic
cells.
The essence of the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis is that the universe we inhabit
is in the process of becoming pervaded with increasingly intelligent life-but
not necessarily human or even human-successor life. Under the theory, the
emergence of life and increasingly competent intelligence are not meaningless
accidents in a hostile, largely lifeless cosmos but at the very heart of the vast
machinery of creation, cosmological evolution, and cosmic replication.
However, the theory does not require or even suggest that the life and intelligence
that emerge be human or human-successor in nature.
The hypothesis simply asserts that the peculiarly life-friendly laws and
constants that prevail in our universe serve a function precisely equivalent to
that of DNA in living creatures on Earth, providing a recipe for development and
a blueprint for the construction of offspring.
Finally, the hypothesis implies that the capacity for the universe to
generate life and to evolve ever more capable intelligence is encoded as a hidden
subtext to the basic laws and constants of nature, stitched like the finest
embroidery into the very fabric of our universe. A corollary-and a key falsifiable
implication of the Selfish Biocosm theory-is that we are likely not alone in
the universe but are probably part of a vast, yet undiscovered transterrestrial
community of lives and intelligences spread across billions of galaxies and
countless parsecs. Under the theory, we share a possible common fate with that
hypothesized community-to help shape the future of the universe and transform
it from a collection of lifeless atoms into a vast, transcendent mind.
The inescapable implication of the Selfish Biocosm hypothesis is that the
immense saga of biological evolution on Earth is one tiny chapter in an ageless
tale of the struggle of the creative force of life against the disintegrative
acid of entropy, of emergent order against encroaching chaos, and ultimately of
the heroic power of mind against the brute intransigence of lifeless matter.
In taking full measure of the seeming miracle of a bio-friendly universe we
should obviously be skeptical of wishful thinking and “just-so” stories. But
we should not be so dismissive of new approaches that we fail to relish the
sense of wonder at the almost miraculous ability of science to fathom mysteries
that once seemed impenetrable-a sense perfectly captured by the great British
innovator Michael Faraday when he summarily dismissed skepticism about his
almost magical ability to summon up the genie of electricity simply by moving a
magnet in a coil of wire.
As Faraday said, “Nothing is too wonderful to be true if it be consistent
with the laws of nature.”
[Non-text portions of this message have been removed]
[Back to Top]
Theosophy World:
Dedicated to the Theosophical Philosophy and its Practical Application