re "self-knowledge," science, and ...
Feb 03, 2004 03:20 PM
by Mauri
The following from Jung's THE
UNDISCOVERED SELF might interest
student's of Theosophy.
<<<<<Most people confuse
"self-knowledge" with knowledge of
their conscious ego personalities.
Anyone who has any ego-consciousness at
all takes it for granted that he knows
himself. But the ego knows only its own
contents, not the unconscious and its
contents. People measure their
self-knowledge by what the average
person in their social environment knows
of himself, but not by the real psychic
facts which are for the most part hidden
from them. In this respect the psyche
behaves like the body with its
physiological and anatomical structure,
of which the average person knows very
little too. Although he lives in it and
with it, most of it is totally unknown
to the layman, and special scientific
knowledge is needed to acquaint
consciousness with what is known of the
body, not to speak of all that is not
known, which also exists.
What is commonly called "self-knowledge"
is therefore a very limited knowledge,
most of it dependent on social factors,
of what goes on in the human psyche.
Hence one is always coming up against
the prejudice that such and such a thing
does not happen "with us" or "in our
family" or among our friends and
acquaintances, and on the other hand,
one meets with equally illusory
assumptions about the alleged presence
of qualities which merely serve to cover
up the true facts of the case. In this
broad belt of unconsciousness, which is
immune to conscious criticism and
control, we stand defenseless, open to
all kinds of influences and psychic
infections. As with all dangers, we can
guard against the risk of psychic
infection only when we know what is
attacking us, and how, where and when
the attack will come. Since
self-knowledge is a matter of getting to
know the individual facts, theories help
very little in this respect. For the
more a theory lays claim to universal
validity, the less capable it is of
doing justice to the individual facts.
Any theory based on experience is
necessarily statistical; that is to
say, it formululcs an ideal average
which abolishes all exceptions at either
end of the scale and replaces them by an
abstract mean. This mean is quite valid,
though it need not necessarily occur in
reality. Despite this it figures in the
theory as an unassailable fundamental
fact. The exceptions at either extreme,
though equally factual, do not appear
in the final result at all, since they
cancel each other out. If, for instance,
I determine the weight of each stone in
a bed of pebbles and get an average
weight of 145 grams, this tells me very
little about the real nature of the
pebbles. Anyone who thought, on the
basis of these findings, that he could
pick up a pebble of 145 grams at the
first try would be in for a serious
disappointment. Indeed, it might well
happen that however long he searched he
would not find a single pebble weighing
exactly 145 grams.
The statistical method shows the facts
in the light of the ideal average but
does not give us a picture of their
empirical reality. While reflecting an
indisputable aspect of reality, it can
falsify the actual truth in a most
misleading way. This is particularly
true of theories which are based on
statistics. The distinctive thing about
real facts, however, is their
individuality. Not to put too fine a
point on it, one could say that the real
picture consists of nothing but
exceptions to the rule, and that, in
consequence, absolute reality has
predominantly the character of irregularity.
These considerations must be borne in
mind whenever there is talk of a theory
serving as a guide to self-knowledge.
There is and can be no self-knowledge
based on theoretical assumptions, for
the object of self-knowledge is an
individual — a relative exception and
an irregular phenomenon. Hence it is not
the universal and the regular that
characterize the individual, but rather
the unique. He is not to be understood
as a recurrent unit but as something
unique and singular which in the last
analysis can neither be known nor
compared with anything else. At the same
time man, as member of a species, can
and must be described as a statistical
unit; otherwise nothing general could be
said about him. For this purpose he has
to be regarded as a comparative unit.
This results in a universally valid
anthropology or psychology, as the case
may be, with an abstract picture of man
as an average unit from which all
individual features have been removed.
But it is precisely these features which
are of paramount importance for
understanding man. If I want to
understand an individual human being, I
must lay aside all scientific knowledge
of the average man and discard all
theories in order to adopt a completely
new and unprejudiced attitude. I can
only approach the task of understanding
with a free and open mind, whereas
knowledge of man, or insight into human
character, presupposes all sorts
of knowledge about mankind in general.
Now whether it is a question of
understanding a fellow human being or of
self-knowledge, I must in both cases
leave all theoretical assumptions behind
me. Since scientific knowledge not only
enjoys universal esteem but, in the
eyes of modern man, counts as the only
intellectual and spiritual authority,
understanding the individual obliges me
to commit
lese majeste', so to speak, to turn a
blind eye to scientific knowledge. This
is a sacrifice not lightly made, for the
scientific attitude cannot rid itself so
easily of its sense of responsibility.
And if the psychologist happens to be a
doctor who wants not only to classify
his patient scientifically but also to
understand him as a human being, he is
threatened with a conflict of duties
between the two diametrically opposed
and mutually exclusive attitudes of
knowledge, on the one hand, and
understanding, on the other. This
conflict cannot be solved by an
either-or but only by a kind of two-way
thinking: doing one thing while not
losing sight of the other.
In view of the fact that in principle,
the positive advantages of knowledge
work specifically to the disadvantage of
understanding, the judgment resulting
therefrom is likely to be something of a
paradox. Judged scientifically, the
individual is nothing but a unit which
repeats itself ad infinitum and could
just as well be designated with a letter
of the alphabet. For understanding, on
the other hand, it is just the unique
individual human being who, when
stripped of all those conformities and
regularities so dear to the heart of the
scientist, is the supreme and only real
object of investigation. >>>>>>
[Back to Top]
Theosophy World:
Dedicated to the Theosophical Philosophy and its Practical Application